LIMITS - FUNCTIONS AND LIMITS - What Is Mathematics? An Elementary Approach to Ideas and Methods, 2nd Edition (1996)

What Is Mathematics? An Elementary Approach to Ideas and Methods, 2nd Edition (1996)

CHAPTER VI. FUNCTIONS AND LIMITS

§2. LIMITS

1. The Limit of a Sequence an

As we have seen in §1, the description of the continuity of a function is based on the limit concept. Up to now we have used this concept in a more or less intuitive form. In this and the following sections we shall consider it in a more systematic way. Since sequences are rather simpler than functions of a continuous variable, we shall begin with a study of sequences.

In Chapter II we encountered sequences an of numbers and studied their limits as n increases indefinitely or “tends to infinity.” For example, the sequence whose nth term is an = 1/n,

(1)

image

has the limit 0 for increasing n:

(2)

image

Let us try to state exactly what is meant by this. As we go out farther and farther in the sequence, the terms become smaller and smaller. After the 100th term all the terms are smaller than 1/100, after the 1000th term all the terms are smaller than 1/1000, and so on. None of the terms is actually equal to 0. But if we go out far enough in the sequence (1), we can be sure that each of its terms will differ from 0 by as little as we please.

The only trouble with this explanation is that the meaning of the italicized phrases is not entirely clear. How far is “far enough,” and how little is “as little as we please”? If we can attach a precise meaning to these phrases then we can give a precise meaning to the limiting relation (2).

A geometric interpretation will help to make the situation clearer. If we represent the terms of the sequence (1) by their corresponding points on the number axis we observe that the terms of the sequence appear to cluster around the point 0. Let us choose any interval I on the number axis with center at the point 0 and total width 2ε, so that the interval extends a distance ε on each side of the point 0. If we choose ε = 10, then, of course, all the terms an = 1/n of the sequence will lie inside the interval I. If we choose ε = 1/10, then the first few terms of the sequence will lie outside I, but all the terms from a11 on,

image

will lie within I. Even if we choose ε = 1/1000, only the first thousand terms of the sequence will fail to lie within I, while from the term a1001 on, all the infinitely many terms

a1001, a1002, a1003, · · ·

will lie within I. Clearly, this reasoning holds for any positive number ε: as soon as a positive ε is chosen, no matter how small it may be, we can then find an integer N so large that

image

From this it follows that all the terms an of the sequence for which nN will lie within I, and only the finite number of terms a1, a2, · · ·, aN–1 can lie outside. The important point is this: First the width of the interval I is assigned at pleasure by choosing ε. Then a suitable integer N can be found. This process of first choosing a number ε and then finding a suitable integer N can be carried out for any positive number ε, no matter how small, and gives a precise meaning to the statement that all the terms of the sequence (1) will differ from 0 by as little as we please, provided we go out far enough in the sequence.

To summarize: Let ε be any positive number. Then we can find an integer N such that all the terms an of the sequence (1) for which nN will lie within the interval I of total width 2ε and with center at the point 0. This is the precise meaning of the limiting relation (2).

On the basis of this example we are now ready to give an exact definition of the general statement: “The sequence of real numbers a1, a2, a3,· · · has the limit a.” We include a in the interior of an interval I of the number axis: if the interval is small, some of the numbers an may lie outside the interval, but as soon as n becomes sufficiently large, say greater than or equal to some integer N, then all the numbers an for which nN must lie within the interval I. Of course, the integer N may have to be taken very large if a very small interval I is chosen, but no matter how small the interval I, such an integer N must exist if the sequence is to have a as its limit.

The fact that a sequence an has the limit a is expressed symbolically by writing

lim an = a asn → ∞,

or simply

ana as n → ∞

(read: an tends to a, or converges to a). The definition of the convergence of a sequence an to a may be formulated more concisely as follows: The sequence a1, a2, a3, · · · has the limit a as n tends to infinity if, corresponding to any positive number ε, no matter how small, there may be found an integer N (depending on ε), such that

(3) |aan| < ε

for all

nN.

This is the abstract formulation of the notion of the limit of a sequence. Small wonder that when confronted with it for the first time one may not fathom it in a few minutes. There is an unfortunate, almost snobbish attitude on the part of some writers of textbooks, who present the reader with this definition without a thorough preparation, as though an explanation were beneath the dignity of a mathematician.

The definition suggests a contest between two persons, A and B. A sets the requirement that the fixed quantity a should be approached by an with a degree of accuracy better than a chosen margin ε = ε1; B meets the requirement by demonstrating that there is a certain integer N = N1 such that all the an after the element aN1 satisfy the ε1-requirement. Then A may become more exacting and set a new, smaller, margin, ε = ε2. B again meets his demand by finding a (perhaps much larger) integer N = N2. If B can satisfy A no matter how small A sets his margin, then we have the situation expressed by an → a.

There is a definite psychological difficulty in grasping this precise definition of limit. Our intuition suggests a “dynamic” idea of a limit as the result of a process of “motion”: we move on through the row of integers 1, 2, 3, · · ·, n, · · · and then observe the behavior of the sequence an. We feel that the approach ana should be observable. But this “natural” attitude is not capable of clear mathematical formulation. To arrive at a precise definition we must reverse the order of steps; instead of first looking at the independent variable n and then at the dependent variable an, we must base our definition on what we have to do if we wish actually to check the statement ana. In such a procedure we must first choose an arbitrarily small margin around a and then determine whether we can meet this condition by taking the independent variable n sufficiently large. Then, by giving symbolic names, ε and N, to the phrases “arbitrarily small margin” and “sufficiently large n,” we are led to the precise definition of limit.

As another example, let us consider the sequence

image

where image. I state that lim an = 1. If you choose an interval whose center is the point 1 and for which ε = 1/10, then I can satisfy your requirement (3) by choosing N = 10; for

image

as soon as n ≥ 10. If you strengthen your demand by choosing ε = 1/1000, then again I can meet it by choosing N = 1000; and similarly for any positive number ε, no matter how small, which you may choose; in fact, I need only choose any integer N greater than 1/ε. This process of assigning an arbitrarily small margin ε about the number a and then proving that the terms of the sequence an are all within a distance ε of a if we go far enough out in the sequence, is the detailed description of the fact that lim an = a.

If the members of the sequence a1, a2, a3, · · · are expressed as infinite decimals, then the statement lim an = a simply means that for any positive integer m the first m digits of an coincide with the first m digits of the infinite decimal expansion of the fixed number a, provided that n is chosen sufficiently large, say greater than or equal to some value N (depending on m). This merely corresponds to choices of ε of the form 10m.

There is another, quite suggestive, way of expressing the limit concept. If lim an = a, and if we enclose a in the interior of an interval I, then no matter how small I may be, all the numbers an for which n is greater than or equal to some integer N will lie within I, so that at most a finite number, N—1, of terms at the beginning of the sequence,

a1, a2,· · ·,aN–1,

can lie outside I. If I is very small, N may be very large, say a hundred or even a thousand billion; still only a finite number of terms of the sequence will lie outside I, while the infinitely many remaining terms will lie within I.

We may say of the members of any infinite sequence that “almost all” have a certain property if only a finite number, no matter how great, do not have the property. For example “almost all” positive integers are greater than 1,000,000,000,000. Using this terminology, the statement lim an= a is equivalent to the statement: If I is any interval with a as its center, then almost all of the numbers an lie within I.

It should be noted in passing that it is not necessarily assumed that all the terms an of a sequence have different values. It is permissible for some, infinitely many, or even all the numbers an to be equal to the limit value a. For example, the sequence for which a1 = 0, a2 = 0, · · ·, an = 0, · · · is a legitimate sequence, and its limit, of course, is 0.

A sequence an with a limit a is called convergent. A sequence an without a limit is called divergent.

Exercises: Prove:

1. The sequence for which image has the limit 0. (Hint: image is less than image and greater than 0.)

2. The sequence image has the limit 0. (Hint: image lies between 0 and image.)

3. The sequence 1, 2, 3, 4, · · · and the oscillating sequences

1, 2, 1, 2, 1, 2,· · ·,

–1, 1,–1, 1,–1, · · · (i.e. an = (–1)n),

and image

do not have limits.

If in a sequence an the members become so large that eventually an is larger than any preassigned number K, then we say that an tends to infinity and write lim an = ∞, or an → ∞. For example, n2 → ∞ and 2n → ∞. This terminology is useful, though perhaps not quite consistent, because ∞ is not considered to be a number a. A sequence tending to infinity is still called divergent.

Exercise: Prove that the sequence image tends to infinity; similarly for image, and Image.

Beginners sometimes fall into the error of thinking that a passage to the limit as n → ∞ may be performed simply by substituting n = ∞ in the expression for an. For example, 1/n → 0 because “1/∞ = 0.” But the symbol ∞ is not a number, and its use in the expression 1/∞ is illegitimate. Trying to imagine the limit of a sequence as the “ultimate” or “last” term an when n = ∞ misses the point and obscures the issue.

2. Monotone Sequences

In the general definition of page 291, no specific type of approach of a convergent sequence a1, a2, a3, · · · to its limit a is required. The simplest type is exhibited by a so-called monotone sequence, such as the sequence

image

Each term of this sequence is greater than the preceding term. For image. A sequence of this sort, where an+1 > an, is said to be monotone increasing. Similarly, a sequence for which an > an+1, such as the sequence 1, 1/2, 1/3, · · ·, is called monotone decreasing. Such sequences can approach their limits from one side only. In contrast to these, there are sequences that oscillate, such as the sequence –1, +1/2, –1/3, +1/4, ···. This sequence approaches its limit 0 from both sides (see Fig. 11, p. 69).

The behavior of a monotone sequence is especially easy to determine. Such a sequence may have no limit, but run away completely, like the sequence

1, 2, 3, 4, · · ·,

where an = n, or the sequence

2, 3, 5, 7, 11, 13, · · ·,

where an is the nth prime number, pn. In this case the sequence tends to infinity. But if the terms of a monotone increasing sequence remain bounded—that is, if every term is less than an upper bound B, known in advance—then it is intuitively clear that the sequence must tend to a certain limit a which will be less than or at most equal to B. We formulate this as the Principle of Monotone Sequences: Any monotone increasing sequence that has an upper bound must converge to a limit. (A similar statement holds for any monotone decreasing sequence with a lower bound.) It is remarkable that the value of the limit need not be given or known in advance; the theorem states that under the prescribed conditions the limit exists. Of course, this theorem depends on the introduction of irrational numbers and would otherwise not always be true; for, as we have seen in Chapter II, any irrational number (such as image) is the limit of the monotone increasing and bounded sequence of rational decimal fractions obtained by breaking off a certain infinite decimal at the nth digit.

image

Fig. 166. Monotone bounded sequence.

* Although the principle of monotone sequences appeals to the intuition as an obvious truth, it will be instructive to give a rigorous proof in the modern fashion. To do this we must show that the principle is a logical consequence of the definitions of real number and limit.

Suppose that the numbers a1, a2, a3,· · · form a monotone increasing but bounded sequence. We can express the terms of this sequence as infinite decimals,

a1 = A1.p1p2p3 · · ·,

a2 = A2.q1q2q3 · · ·,

a3 = A3.r1r2r3 · · ·,

..............................

where the Ai are integers and the pi, qi, etc. are digits from 0 to 9. Now run down the column of integers A1, A2, A3, · · ·. Since the sequence a1, a2, a3, · · · is bounded, these integers cannot increase indefinitely, and since the sequence is monotone increasing, the sequence of integers A1, A2,A3, · · · will remain constant after attaining its maximum value. Call this maximum value A, and suppose that it is attained at the N0th row. Now run down the second column p1,, q1, r1, · · ·, confining attention to the terms of the Noth and subsequent rows. If x1 is the largest digit to appear in this column after the Noth row, then x1 will appear constantly after its first appearance, which we may suppose to occur in the N1th row, where N1No. For if the digit in this column decreased at any time thereafter, the sequence a1, a2, a3, · · · would not be monotone increasing. Next we consider the digits p2,, q2, r2, · · · of the third column. A similar argument shows that after a certain integer N2N1 the digits of the third column are constantly equal to some digit x2. If we repeat this process for the 4th, 5th, · · · columns we obtain digits x3, x4, x5, · · · and corresponding integers N3, N4, N5, · · ·. It is easy to see that the number

a = A.x1x2x3x4 · · ·

is the limit of the sequence a1, a2, a3, · · ·. For if ε is chosen ≥ 10m, then for all nNm the integral part and first m places of digits after the decimal point in an will coincide with those of a, so that the difference | aan | cannot exceed 10m. Since this can be done for any positive ε, however small, by choosing m sufficiently large, the theorem is proved.

It is also possible to prove this theorem on the basis of any one of the other definitions of real numbers given in Chapter II; for example, the definition by nested intervals or by Dedekind cuts. Such proofs are to be found in most texts on advanced calculus.

The principle of monotone sequences could have been used in Chapter II to define the sum and product of two positive infinite decimals,

a = A.a1 a2 a3 · · ·,

b = B.b1 b2 b3 · · ·.

Two such expressions cannot be added or multiplied in the ordinary way, starting from the right-hand end, for there is no such end. (As an example, the reader may try to add the two infinite decimals 0.333333 · · ·and 0.989898 · · ·.) But if xn denotes the finite decimal fraction obtained by breaking off the expressions for a and b at the nth place and adding in the ordinary way, then the sequence x1, x2, x3,· · · will be monotone increasing and bounded (by the integer A + B + 2, for example). Hence this sequence has a limit, and we may define a + b = lim xn. A similar process serves to define the product ab. These definitions can then be extended by the ordinary rules of arithmetic to cover all cases, where a and b are positive or negative.

Exercise: Show in this way that the sum of the two infinite decimals considered above is the real number 1.323232 · · · = 131/99.

The importance of the limit concept in mathematics lies in the fact that many numbers are defined only as limits—often as limits of monotone bounded sequences. This is why the field of rational numbers, in which such limits may not exist, is too narrow for the needs of mathematics.

3. Euler’s Number e

The number e has had an established place in mathematics alongside the Archimedean number π ever since the publication in 1748 of Euler’s Introductio in Analysin Infinitorum. It provides an excellent illustration of how the principle of monotone sequences can serve to define a new real number. Using the abbreviation

n! = 1.2.3.4 · · · n

for the product of the first n integers, we consider the sequence a1, a2, a3, · · ·, where

(4)

image

The terms an form a monotone increasing sequence, since an+1 originates from an by the addition of the positive increment image. Moreover, the values of an are bounded above:

(5)  an B < = 3.

For we have image

and hence

image

using the formula given on page 13 for the sum of the first n terms of a geometric series. Hence, by the principle of monotone sequences, an must approach a limit as n tends to infinity, and this limit we call e. To express the fact that e = lim an, we may write e as the “infinite series”

(6)  image

This “equality,” with a row of dots at the end, is simply another way of expressing the content of the two statements

image

and

ane as n → ∞.

The series (6) permits the calculation of e to any desired degree of accuracy. For example, the sum (to nine digits) of the terms in (6) up to and including 1/12! is Σ = 2.71828183 · · ·. (The reader should check this result.) The “error,” i.e. the difference between this value and the true value of e can easily be appraised. We have for the difference (e – Σ) the expression

image

This is so small that it cannot affect the ninth digit of Σ. Hence, allowing for a possible error in the last figure of the value given above, we have e = 2.7182818, to eight digits.

* The number e is irrational. To prove this we shall proceed indirectly by assuming that e = p/q, where p and q are integers, and then deducing an absurdity from this assumption. Since we know that 2 < e < 3, e cannot be an integer, and therefore q must be at least equal to 2. Now we multiply both sides of (6) by q! = 2.3 · · · q, obtaining

(7) image

On the left side we obviously have an integer. On the right side, the term in brackets is likewise an integer. The remainder of the right side, however, is a positive number that is less than image and hence no integer. For q ≥ 2, and hence the terms of the series 1/(q + 1) + · · · are respectively not greater than the corresponding terms of the geometrical series 1/3 + 1/32 + 1/33 + · · ·, whose sum is image. Hence (7) presents a contradiction: the integer on the left side cannot be equal to the number on the right side; for this latter number, being the sum of an integer and a positive number less than image, is not an integer.

4. The Number π

As is known from school mathematics, the length of the circumference of a circle of unit radius can be defined as the limit of a sequence of lengths of regular polygons with an increasing number of sides. The length of the circumference so defined is denoted by 2π. More precisely, if pndenotes the length of the inscribed, and qn the length of the circumscribed regular n-sided polygon, then pn < 2π < qn. Moreover, as n increases, each of the sequences pn, qn approaches monotonically, and with each step we obtain a smaller margin for the error in the approximation of 2π given by pn or qn.

On page 124 we found the expression

image

containing m – 1 nested square root signs. This formula can be used to compute the approximate value of 2π.

image

Fig. 167. Circle approximated by polygons.

Exercises: 1. Find the approximate value of π given by p4, p8, and p16.

* 2. Find a formula for q2m.

* 3. Use this formula to find q4, q8, and q16.

From a knowledge of p16 and q16, state bounds between which π must lie.

What is the number π? The inequality pn < 2π < qn gives the complete answer by setting up a sequence of nested intervals which close down on the point 2π. Still, this answer leaves something to be desired, for it gives no information about the nature of π as a real number: is it rational or irrational, algebraic or transcendental? As we have mentioned on page 140, π is in fact a transcendental number, and hence irrational. In contrast to the proof for e, the proof of the irrationality of π, first given by J. H. Lambert (1728-1777), is rather difficult and will not be undertaken here. However, other information about π is within our reach. Recalling the statement that the integers are the basic material of mathematics, we may ask whether the number π has any simple relationship to the integers. The decimal expansion of π, although it has been calculated to several hundred places, reveals no trace of regularity. This is not surprising, since π and 10 have nothing to do with one another. But in the eighteenth century Euler and others found beautiful expressions linking π to the integers by means of infinite series and products. Perhaps the simplest such formula is the following:

image

expressing π/4 as the limit for increasing n of the partial sums

image

We shall derive this formula in Chapter VIII. Another infinite series for π is

image

Still another striking expression for π was discovered by the English mathematician John Wallis (1616-1703). His formula states that

image

This is sometimes written in the abbreviated form

image

the expression on the right being called an infinite product.

A proof of the last two formulas will be found in any comprehensive book on the calculus (see p.482 and pp. 509-510).

*5. Continued Fractions

Interesting limiting processes occur in connection with continued fractions. A finite continued fraction, such as

image

represents a rational number. On page 49 we showed that every rational number can be written in this form by means of the Euclidean algorithm. For irrational numbers, however, the algorithm does not stop after a finite number of steps. Instead, it leads to a sequence of fractions of increasing length, each representing a rational number. In particular, all real algebraic numbers (see p. 103) of degree 2 may be expressed in this way. Consider, for example, the number image, which is a root of the quadratic equation

image

If on the right side x is again replaced by 1/(2 + x) this yields the expression

image

and then

image

and so on, so that after n steps we obtain the equation

image

As n tends to infinity, we obtain the “infinite continued fraction”

image

This remarkable formula connects image with the integers in a much more striking way than does the decimal expansion of image, which displays no regularity in the succession of its digits.

For the positive root of any quadratic equation of the form

image

we obtain the expansion

image

For example, setting a = 1, we find

image

(cf. p. 123). These examples are special cases of a general theorem which states that the real roots of quadratic equations with integral coefficients have periodic continued fraction developments, just as rational numbers have periodic decimal expansions.

Euler was able to find almost equally simple infinite continued fractions for e and π. The following are exhibited without proof:

image

image